• MarxMadness [comrade/them]
    ·
    3 years ago

    Years ago, anthropologist Margaret Mead was asked by a student what she considered to be the first sign of civilization in a culture. The student expected Mead to talk about fishhooks or clay pots or grinding stones.

    But no. Mead said that the first sign of civilization in an ancient culture was a femur (thighbone) that had been broken and then healed. Mead explained that in the animal kingdom, if you break your leg, you die. You cannot run from danger, get to the river for a drink or hunt for food. You are meat for prowling beasts. No animal survives a broken leg long enough for the bone to heal.

    A broken femur that has healed is evidence that someone has taken time to stay with the one who fell, has bound up the wound, has carried the person to safety and has tended the person through recovery. Helping someone else through difficulty is where civilization starts, Mead said.”

    https://stacyhackner.wordpress.com/2020/04/21/that-margaret-mead-quote/

    • jack [he/him, comrade/them]
      ·
      3 years ago

      I mean, some animals definitely do survive those injuries. There's a reason so many animals are physiologically capable of it.

      But still, she's right.

  • Nakoichi [they/them]
    ·
    3 years ago

    Debt by David Graeber is a good book that touches on that topic a lot.

    • Llituro [he/him, they/them]
      ·
      3 years ago

      Yep, was also going to say Debt. The mUh HuMaN nAtuRe argument is just annihilated again and again and again in that book. There's also a talk on YouTube that Graeber did with an archaeologist and they touch on some more archaeological examples of societies that decimate our concepts of human society, including one group that lived in communistic, orgy-bands in the summer and regrouped into hierarchical society complete with a ruling family heredity and police functions in the winter. Crazy shit. Humans can make pretty much anything work as long as everyone can believe in it enough for it to have its own momentum, and if it doesn't have so many contradictions that it begins to literally rip apart the earth.

  • Dimmer06 [he/him,comrade/them]
    ·
    edit-2
    3 years ago

    Idk much about anthropology, but tragedy of the commons is idealist nonsense. There literally was the commons in England that was used by yeoman farmers for centuries without over grazing and the only tragedy that ever happened to it was its appropriation, enclosure by the capitalist. There is bourgeois nature which infects us all to varying degrees, but that is a product of the mode of production we live under and to assume it is inherent is blatantly ahistorical, never mind anti-dialectical. Did the feudal peasant think any man could become a lord if they just worked hard enough just as so many bourgeois ideologues think they can become wealthy if they work hard enough? No of course not. The peasant thought the lord was ordained by god (or the smarter among them recognized they were ordained by force of arms). The peasant would never be ordained by god to be a lord, he was made to be a serf and so he should behave as a serf. This simple fact proves that bourgeois ideology (so called "human nature") is not universal, merely an artifact of our current time. Human nature changes!

    So what then, will change our bourgeois conscious to something egalitarian? Idk. maybe revolutionary struggle and the massive expansion of the means of production so as to adequately meet everyone's needs. The abolition of the value-form (money), along with the end of commodity production, the end of production of goods for exchange to be replaced by production of goods for use might bring about this change.

    Of course you only have to look at historical precedent to see that without such a massive surplus of labor-power for sale on the market and division of labor, generalized commodity production did not take place. Did the Mohawk catch all the fish to sell to the Seneca? No. Did the Mongols breed horses to sell to the Chinese? No. If it were human nature to maximize profit then these peoples should have done these things!

    "Collectivism" is too broad of an abstraction to mount a defense of. The capitalist state is a collective with a military, infrastructure, postal service, police, and fire departments owned in common. The social division of labor forces a collective approach to the maintenance of society, for if I bake bread, I must trade with the farmer for grain. If I wish to live near someone else without warring against them, then we must adhere to a common set of rules and norms known as a social contract which is developed collectively.

  • Civility [none/use name]
    ·
    3 years ago

    The theory was written by ya boi :kropotkin-shining: in his 1902 essay Mutual Aid: A Factor of Evolution but that's not gonna mean anything to a chud.

    Basically, one of humans largest evolutionary advantages over even other higher primates is just how much we help each other.

    Tool making and creative problem solving aren't actually that unique in Animalia. Lots of different species do them to varying degrees.

    The two most unique things about humans, evolutionary speaking, especially compared to other primates and even other hominids is that we share information, teach and learn skills from not only our family members but our peers, and that we have developed the most complex languages and societies we've ever discovered on this planet to facilitate that.

    Screwing people over feels shitty, helping people feels good. That's human nature.

    Our ability to organise on a massive scale (surpassed by ants, arguably the other most successful species on the planet) and share altruistically is what has allowed humans to dominate Earth. That we've somehow managed to use those complex communication and organisation abilities to override our natural drive to altruism is deeply ironic, utterly unnatural and the largest threat we, as a species have ever faced.

  • FidelCashflow [he/him]
    ·
    edit-2
    3 years ago

    This is understandable we are taught from a young age that competition leads to success. It is almost never though.

    Fuck it though. Run with it. Tell them we are ment to live red in tooth and claw. That is why we need to take billionairs money from them. They got the system fucked up and aren't having to struggle so they can't reach their full potential.

  • Fakename_Bill [he/him]
    ·
    edit-2
    3 years ago

    Selfishness and greed are not “human nature.” Self-preservation is human nature. In a capitalist society that rewards ruthless competition and leaves the poor to suffer and die, this drive for self-preservation manifests as selfish behavior at the expense of others. If we lived in a society that punished selfish behavior and rewarded actions that benefit the collective, selfish behavior would be much less common.

    I think the core element of our capitalist society that fosters selfishness is the utter irrationality of our economic system. You can do all the “right things,” plan out your life in the perfect way that’s *supposed* to lead to success, and still get screwed. Even if you’re living a comfortable life, you could lose it all at any moment for reasons completely outside of your control. No financial cushion is ever big enough.

  • safflower [she/her]
    ·
    edit-2
    3 years ago

    I'm not an expert, but I'm reading an amazing anthropology book, it's called In and Out of Each Other's Bodies : Theory of Mind, Evolution, Truth, and the Nature of the Social, by Maurice Bloch, a Marxist anthropologist. He talks about the difficulty of isolating individual life forms for species such as coral reefs or bees. He asks, is it the bee or the hive that is the animal? Afterall, the bees in a hive are as genetically identical as are the different bits of the human body, and a hive possesses only one set of working reproductive organs. He argues how social animals, but especially humans, "go in and out of each other's bodies" in three different ways- sexually, reproductively (birth), and neurologically. The latter one of course is the most mysterious way, but he shows how neurologically, when we communicate with each other, we materially change the chemical structure of each other's brains. He goes into much more wonderful depth that I have time to describe here, but I highly recommend it.

    He also talks about a 'theory of mind' which is particularly relevant to your q, I think. As I've said, I'm in a rush. So I'm going to copy and paste an excerpt for you to use for further research, if you would like (sorry for the length!):

    "This chapter, however, will not pursue the implications of the link between the fact that we go in and out of each other’s bodies in birth and sex and the cultural representa-tions of this fact in kinship systems. Many (I do not include myself among them) might feel that this topic has grown tiresome. I merely evoke the controversy to stress that be-cause all cultures interpret, and have to interpret, the fact that we go in and out of each other in sex and birth, they also have to interpret the consequent fact that for us (as with coral) there is indeterminacy concerning the physical boundaries of individuals. For instance, the so-called “de-scent theorists” of my anthropological youth were fascinated with groups of people who declare themselves to be “one body”; in other words, corporate groups. These statements are interesting not because they are flights of fancy proving yet again that the world we live in is culturally constructed but because they are in part motivated by the very real fact of the indeterminacy and arbitrariness of the boundaries of biological units.

    My focus in this chapter concerns another real fact about human beings that, although it concerns a matter different from kinship, is not altogether unrelated to it. Indeterminacy and arbitrariness of boundaries are not simply the result of the sexual character of our species and the way it repro-duces itself. They are also due to another feature of Homo sapiens. Individuals go in and out of each other because of certain characteristics of the human nervous system. This form of interpenetration is as material as sex and birth; but unlike sex and birth it is more or less unique to our species (Povinelli et al. 2000; Decety and Somerville 2003).I have already mentioned that, although the boundaries of individual units are arbitrary among all living forms, this ambiguity takes on a special, perhaps more extreme form in social animals because the social—of itself and by defi-nition—continually reconnects the individuals whom time and genealogical distance are separating. Such a process occurs in a variety of ways in different life forms because of the mechanisms that make the social differ according to the species concerned. So it is not surprising that the specific basis of human sociability is a product of those capacities of our species that make it distinctive (Humphrey 2002).

    One thing that normal human babies do at about 1 year old, but our nearest relatives, the chimpanzees, never do, is point at things, not because they want what they desig-nate—they do this, but so do chimps—but because they want the people around them to pay attention to the same things. In other words, they want the people they are with to adjust their minds in harmony with theirs—in short, to share intentionality (Gopnik 1993; Tomasello and Rakoczy 2003; Tomasello 1999). This demonstrative pointing is one of the first stages of the development of that unique and probably most important of human capacities: the ability to “read” the mind of others, a capacity that is somewhat oddly referred to as “theory of mind” (TOM for short). This ability continues to develop from the age of 12 months on until the child reaches the age when it can be shown that the child “knows” that other people act in terms of the be-liefs or concepts they hold, rather than in terms of how the world is (Wimmer and Perner 1983). By “know,” I simply mean that the child and, of course, the adult, acts in terms of their reading of the beliefs of alter and continually adjusts her behavior accordingly. I do not mean that the person who does this is necessarily conscious of the process (a point to which I shall return in a moment). The whole process is far too complex and too rapid for that to be possible. Nonethe-less, the importance of TOM can hardly be overestimated. Those familiar with Gricean theories of linguistic pragmatics will realize that it can be argued, convincingly in my opinion, that this continual mind reading is what makes linguistic communication, and indeed all complex human communica-tion, possible (Sperber and Wilson 1986).It is legitimate to think that to talk of the mutual mind reading on which our social life is based is, at best, simply a metaphor; at worst, a mystification. However, I want to stress that the metaphor refers to an empirical phenomenon of interpenetration, even though admittedly we don’t stick our finger into each other’s brains in some kind of mental intercourse.

    • safflower [she/her]
      ·
      3 years ago

      2/2 Just how material the process of mind reading may be has become clearer in the light of recent neurological findings. For instance, many researchers now argue that the unique human ability to read the mind of those with whom we in-teract is ultimately based on a much more general feature of the brain that is not confined to humans: the so-called “mirror neurones” (Gallese and Goldman 1998).Perhaps the term is misleading. What is being referred to is an observation that has been made possible by modern neural imagery. The term mirror neurones means that exactly the same neurones are activated in our brains when, for example, we see someone raising their arm to point at the ceiling as when we perform the action ourselves. In other words, the action of alter requires from us a part of the same physiological process: the neural part as the action of ego.Indeed, a moment’s reflection makes us realize that, even without the arcane and somewhat contested biology of mirror neurones, the very nature of human communication mustinvolve something like this (Decety and Somerville 2003).3Let us consider a simple act of linguistic communica-tion. Here I follow Sperber and Wilson’s theory of relevance fairly closely (Sperber and Wilson 1986). For my message to come across when I say, for example: “Today we honor the memory of Roy Rappaport” a mechanism must occur that enables you to penetrate my brain and align yours so that its neuronal organization resembles mine. In order to do this, we both had to use a tool, sound waves in this case, but it cannot possibly be the sound waves, as such, that carried my meaning to you. Sound waves, poor things, are just sound waves. The reality is that sound waves enable me to modify your brain, or mind, so that its neuronal organization in part resembles mine, admittedly in a very limited way. And, of course, the ability to communicate in this way—to connect our neurones—is what makes culture possible because cul-ture must ultimately be based on the exchange of informa-tion. This can then be combined with other information and then transformed or reproduced through time and across space in a uniquely human way.The parallel neuronal modification implied by communica-tion has further important implications. Let us assume, for the sake of argument, that it is possible for an individual to create ex nihilo a representation. Such a representation could then be said to be under that individual’s control because the process that produced it would be hers alone. However, when the representation comes from someone else’s brain (i.e., when it comes via the process of communication, which is in fact always the case, though to varying extents), the representation of one brain colonizes another. This process, whether it is conscious or subconscious, is the basis of all communication. In such a case, the created neuronal activ-ity of one brain is the material existing in another. By this means, the brains of different individuals interpenetrate materially so that the boundaries that we believe to be obvi-ous become problematic. What I am saying is very similar to what some writers, especially Ed Hutchins, call “distributed cognition” (Hutchins 1995). However, I would distance my argument from them on one minor point. Hutchins, in talking about this phenomenon, likes to refer to minds “not bounded by the skin” as if some sort of extra-biological process ex-isted. I am too literal-minded to feel comfortable with such phraseology, which makes the process in question appear surreal. The process of interpenetration I am discussing is straightforward and biological.

      My other difference from the distributed cognition folks is not a disagreement; I simply would like to push their insights further. Hutchins is famous for his demonstration of the way the knowledge necessary to navigate a big ship is not held in the head of any one crew member; it is distributed in a group. In an action such as coping with an emergency, each individual does his job as best he can in the light of his own knowledge, but in doing so he relies on other individu-als who have other bits of knowledge necessary to navigate the ship that he does not and does not need to have. This is what Hutchins calls distributed cognition. For this type of reliance on the knowledge of others to be possible, the differ-ent individuals need to trust that the others know what they are doing and are well intentioned. This means that people can then act on what they know is incomplete knowledge, but which they trust is completed by the knowledge others have, to the extent of acting on that which they do not need fully to understand. It is not that they rely wholly on others; they rely on others at the very moment they rely on their own knowledge.

      By using this particular formulation, I deliberately align what I am saying with the point made by a group of phi-losophers who, following Hilary Putnam and the “deference” theorists, stress that social life is based on trust of others; basically on the default assumption that these others with whom we are in contact are normally competent and coopera-tive. In other words, because of our theory of mind adapta-tion, we continually interpenetrate as we communicate and hold as true information that makes sense only because it is also contained or continuous with that in other minds (Put-nam 1975; Burge 1993; Orrigi 2000). This is the nature of human cognition, which is essentially social. Such a state of affairs makes it possible that the content of knowledge stored in an individual is not to be understood nor consciously sought to be understood, but this individual is likely to be aware of the solidarity on which the whole system of social cognition is based, and this may be greatly valued. This is a point to which I shall return."

      I hope that helps some! I find it extremely fascinating.